1995 POLNTS OF VIEWSSTEMATIC BIOLOG schoois ot taxonomy (Fig. 1) are as foliows. Aristotelian taxonomy proceeds by logical subdivision, in which each member of a Cladistic Taxonomy, Phylogenetic Systematics, and Evolutionary Ranking pair of taxa is characterized, respectively, by the presence and absence of a chosen N Dt feature. All present attempts to derive a taxonom from an identitication key reflect this process. In Linnaean taxonomy, there is an explicit attempt to distinguish the im- portant (stable, essential) properties from the unimportant (variable, nonessential) properties. In traditional taxonomy, groups are reconstructed based on perceived sim- ilarities and ditterences among taxa. Qui- narian taxonomists (eg., MacLeay, 1819) looked for idealistic groupings in circles of five, supposed to reveal the harmonious MARTIN L. CHRISTOFFERSEN nEto a SISt£MT ITA t Ecoioga. uniersuzae keaETa. ia Paraiva 5S050-900. joào Pessoa. Paraiba Bras1l A The anaent discipline of biological tax onomr has been veT slow to incorporate phylogenetic representations (Gritfiths, maior shifts in worid views throughout the millennia. imperiious to the derision of saentists trom the more giamorous fields 0 research. marnr taxonomists today sim- onvmy tied to Linnaean categories, and re- pi take tor graried secular traditions of dundant taxon names (Christoftersen, describing and naming the diversity of na- Te Ther mav persist stoically for a life- conflict with evolutionary approaches. The time in such a sel:-appointed descriptive codes thus help perpetuate essential1stic role, avoiding theor, philosophy, and ex taxonomic traditions rather than promote pianation. Some of these taxonomists may Conceptual evolutionary nnovations. rated by the codes, simply conflict with 1974a, 1974b, 1976). For exampie, manda- tor categories, the names o: genera as parts of binomiais, typification and syn- FiGURE 1. A possible phyiogenv o: intellectual lin- eages in biological taxonorn. A-M. sequence of an- cestor-descendant lineages; N monophyletic taxon of multiple lineages or single lineage o 11nterbreedng populations. A = Aristotelian taxonomy; B = Linnae- an (essentialistic, typolog1cal) taxonomy, C = tradi- tional taxonomy; D = extinct qunarnan taxonomy; E conventional taxonomy; F= 0mnispeciive tcompi- latory, practical, utilitarian) taxononir, G = natural Od LdXOnomy nvolves interpretation of taxonomy; H = phenetic (numencal taxonomy (phe similarities and differences as reflecting netics);= orthodox taxonomy,! = evoiunonary degrees of phylogenetic relationships. Om- (Mavrian, Simpsonian, sVntheic, siTICTetistic. gradis- tic, eclectic) taxonomy (phyletics), K = Hennigian tax- onomy, L phylogernetic taxonOny iphylogenetic cia distics), M=ciadisti: taonomy patterr. methodoiogica., transtormed ). = phyiogeneuc svs tematics (pnvlogenetics and lawful relations of numbers as evi- dence of the rational plan of creation. In- Corporating evolutionary theory, conven- 1987; de Queiroz and Gauthier, 1992) all nispective taxonomists explicity reject arny connections between a practical and utili- tarian taxonomy and the processes thought to be responsible for biological di- versitt eS. Biackweider, 1964). In natural taxonom, groups are supposed to be dis- COvered in nature rather than fabricated in venture intuitive classitications tor their CONCETUAL LINEAGES named groups bu: will often delegate to otners the task 0: derivVing evolutionar meanings rom the: propOsals. EvolunOnarv concepts have still not pen etrated tne core 0: nomenclature. The in- tlicting conceptual systems. Following ternationa. coaes (internationai Commis- Hull's (1984) and Mishler's (198:) analog Sion on Loological Nomnenclature, 1985; Lnternat1onal Botanica Congress, 1988; in- research groups, rather than being defined ternational Associaion of Microbial Soci- by the presence of Some necessary and sut eties, 1992 are totaly couched in a tradi- ficient set of shared ideas, are viewed as tional Linnaean ramewOrk developed more than 100 vea:s before the widespread acceptarnce oi evOiutionary ideas. Purport- relations with other lineages. I propose a ediy not to interIere with taxonomic free- dom, the codesprovide no rules for the svstems of biological taxonomr (Fig. 1). Fo: Tecógnition and derinition of taxa and cat- egores et the available rules significantly Constrain taxonomic practice by tving tax- (individual spokespersons) on the phylo- ot names to categorical ranks. This struc- ture interteres wjtn the codes own avowed who provided a numerical cladistic studv goals of providing expiicit, universal, and of phylogeneticists and a review' of prei stablenames tor taxonomy because a taxon ous single-character classifications of the ame must be changed every time it is three main contemporary schools of tax placed in a different category (de Queiroz onom. and Gauthier, 1994). Furthermore, several taxonomic conventions, variously incorpo- atics, and classification have been advocat- laxonomists, like other segments of the scientific community, are presently divid- ed into several tactions that support con- 1970; Griffiths, 1974a; Wile, 1981: de the mind of the taxonomist. Phenetic tax- Queiroz, 1988). When these denominations onomists attempt to quantify data and es- become interehangeably qualined by such tablish groups by overall similarity. In or- terms as traditional, numerical, phenetic, evolutionary, cladistic, and phylogenetic used to access taxa (similarity, diversity, (Fig. 1), their meanings become fmulti�ari- Size of gaps, ecology, behavior, etc.). In ous, extensively Overlapping. and sutti- evolutionary taxonomy, species are rede- Ciently confusing So as to lose much of fined as evolutionary units (MayT, 1942, their heuristic and interpretative value íct. Simpson, 1961), and phenetic, Patristic, Charig, 1982; Hill and Crane. 1982; de and cladistic data are combined into a Sin- Queiroz and Donoghue, 1090b: Nixon and gle taxonomic system (e.g., May, 1981; Wheeler, 1990). lerms and concepts are necessarily context bound and shouid be allowed to change through time. I provide granted a central role at all levels in the here successively more inciusive defini- taxonomic hierarchy. in the last two de- tions for the basic concepts of taxonomy, systematics, and Classification. I hope my assignment of several commonly used Mishler, 1987; de Queiroz and Donoghue, qualitying terms to distinct conceptual 1990a) (Fig. 1). Pattern cladists are empir systems (Fig. 1) wll reduce ambiguity, even if total agreement is not possible. Brief haracterizaions ot the sereral a taxonomy (Brady, 1985; Nelson, 1985. with biological phylogenies, tnese difterent thodox taxonomy, multiple criteria are intellectual lineages, with strong historicai Conerence, social! cohesion, and adversaria. tentative phvlogeny tor these intellectua. those that would have prererred to see characters (shared ideas) and Characters Stuessy, 1987, 1990). In Hernigian taxono- my, the priniple of common descent is genetic tree, I deier to Carpenter (1987: cades, a phiosophical split has developed within phylogenetic systematics e.g Different concepts of taxonomy, system- ICists that avoid all assumpthons and pre- Conceptions about process in constructing ed by various authors (e.g., Simpson, 196. Blackwelder, 1967; Mayr, 1969; Nelsor mal endii nrufpb bitnet. SYSTEMATIC BIOLOG VOL. 1995 POINTS OF VIEW 42 avoiding the time axis and the production practices. Cladistic taxonomy mav be iden-tified with what has been called the taxic Rieppel, 1988b). Phyiogenetic taxonomists (Hennig. 1966:6). Characters are instanta are evoiutionary theorists that deduce the neous morphologies (de Queiroz, 1985: most useful taxonomic concepts and meth- 296) that are compared among "specimens ods from general evolutionary processes at similar